Dear all,
this Friday we have our symposium "Science and Politics" as part of the
Dissertant*innenseminar. We start again at 2pm at the Verein (Campus,
Hof 1, Eingang 1.2). Unfortunately, there will be only two talks,
because Silke Körber had to withdraw for health reasons (best wishes to
Silke: get well soon!). This will be the schedule now:
2-3pm: Bianca Crewe (UBC Vancouver): The Symbolic View of Science and
its Application in Politics
3-4pm: Christian Damböck (IVC): Fascism as Illogical Reasoning. Rudolf
Carnap's Forgotten Approach
I add abstracts to this email and attach the paper for the second talk.
To those of you interested in Neue Sachlichkeit, here also a reminder to
the book presentation for Hans-Joachim Dahms (ed.), /Franz Roh
1890-1965. Eine Kollektivbiografie/, which takes place tomorrow,
Thursday, 5pm, at the IWK (in German):
https://www.iwk.ac.at/events/franz-roh-1890-1965-kunstkritiker-vorkaempfer-…
best wishes and see you soon
Christian
*Symposium "Science and Politics", Vienna Circle Society (Campus, Hof 1,
Eingang 1.2), Friday, December 6, 2pm:*
2pm: Bianca Crewe (UBC Vancouver): The Symbolic View of Science and its
Application in Politics
It is now common knowledge that a sea-change occurred in the philosophy
of science towards the end of the nineteenth century. Many philosophers
of this era characterize the preceding paradigm as mechanisticor
materialist, in reference to the philosophical outlook, derived by
science and presupposed by science, that suggests a specific view of the
methods, aims, and standards of intelligibility in science and
epistemology. Here, I will describe how this paradigm operates in the
work of three representatives of philosophy in the twentieth century:
Ernst Cassirer, Alfred North Whitehead, and Philipp Frank. These figures
position themselves as overcoming mechanistic philosophy through an
understanding of science as symbolic. I focus on how their broadly
functionalist, semiotic views develop out of reflections on the methods
of the physical sciences in the second half of the nineteenth century
(particularly electromagnetic theory), and how this is taken up in their
later work in considerations of the role of symbols in politics and
culture more generally. All three, I argue, have a critical project in
common, aimed at freedom from historically conditioned symbols. The
primary tool they use in this project is narratives of the history of
philosophy of science.
In the case of Whitehead, my focus is primarily on two lecture series’,
published respectively as Science and the Modern World in 1925, and
Symbolism: its Meaning and Effect in 1927. My focus in Cassirer will be
his application of symbolic forms to nationalism, and in the case of
Frank, I will offer a reading of his symbolic view of science in service
of a humanistic project “synthesizing” the sciences with other parts of
human culture, without just latching onto evocative general terminology
in the sciences (like matter, energy, etc.) to do so. This project moves
to recognize the centrality of the concept of the symbol in twentieth
century philosophy; its genesis, and its common place in the work of
seemingly diverse philosophers, towards a different thematic emphasis in
the history of analytic philosophy and the history of philosophy of science.
3pm: Christian Damböck (IVC): Fascism as Illogical Reasoning. Rudolf
Carnap's Forgotten Approach
In his now completely forgotten contribution to the Harvard Tercentenary
Celebration in 1936, Rudolf Carnap outlines a theory of illogical
reasoning that can be interpreted as a theory of fascist politics. While
theories of fascism often see the loss of humanistic values as the
primary problem, Carnap sees the values of humanism as natural
components of the scientific world conception, so that anti-humanism and
fascism can only arise as a consequence of the loss of the latter.
According to Carnap, illogical thinking occurs in three forms: (a)
political attitudes are disguised as facts or destiny, (b) inconsistent
or logically misconstrued value systems are accepted, (c) insufficiently
confirmed or empirically false premises are taken as a basis. Fascism
arises from propaganda that spreads illogical thinking in society. I
contextualize Carnap's 1936 approach to explain why it was not pursued
further and why value-based theories of fascism continue to prevail
today. On this basis, I also outline some consequences of a Carnapian
understanding of fascism for contemporary politics.